Euthyphro dilemma
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
The Euthyphro dilemma is found in Plato's dialogue Euthyphro, in which Socrates asks Euthyphro: “Is the pious loved by the gods because it is pious, or is it pious because it is loved by the gods?” In monotheistic terms, this is usually transformed into: “Is what is moral commanded by God because it is moral, or is it moral because it's commanded by God?”.
Contents |
[edit] The dilemma in Plato
In Euthyphro, Socrates and Euthyphro are discussing the nature of the pious. Euthyphro agrees to the proposal that the pious is the same thing as the god-loved, but Socrates finds a problem with this proposal. Clearly, the reason that the god-loved is god-loved is that the gods love it — this fact is what makes the god-loved god-loved. But we cannot likewise say that the reason why the pious is pious is that the gods love it. For, as Socrates presumes and Euthyphro agrees, the gods love the pious because it is pious (both parties agree on this, the second horn of the dilemma). And you can't have it both ways — you can't say that the gods love the pious because it is pious, and then add that the pious is pious because the gods love it, for this would be viciously circular. So, since what makes the god-loved god-loved is not what makes the pious pious, it follows that the god-loved and the pious are not the same thing — they do not have the same nature. Socrates admits that the proposal under discussion might give us a mere feature of the pious, but insists that it does not give us the nature of the pious.
[edit] Explanation of the dilemma
The first horn of the dilemma implies that morality is independent of God and, indeed, that God is bound by morality just as his creatures are. God then becomes little more than a passer-on of moral knowledge.
The second horn of the dilemma (known as divine command theory) runs into three main problems. First, it implies that what is good is arbitrary, based merely upon God's whim and no higher morality; if God had created the world to include the values that rape, murder, and torture were virtues, while mercy and charity were vices, then they would have been. Secondly, it implies that calling God good makes no sense (or, at best, that one is simply saying that God is consistent). Thirdly, alteribility of God's commands, i.e. God could have commanded anything and it would be considered moral.
All of these dilemmas have been solved by modern philosophers:
Arbitrariness: Even if god does not have a moral reason to command than you could say they have some other reason for their existence God’s commandments are restrained. For every commandment there’s a prior moral reason (set by God). Nothing in logic tells you that if every moral fact was brought into being by divine commandment, that any moral fact need have no reason for it, even if its based on another moral fact.
Alterability (The Parallel argument): As Divine Command Ethicists you must believe that anything God commands is moral. So anything God commands could (hypothetically such as vivisecting babies) be moral. One cannot draw any conclusions about counterfactuals because their conditionals are false. e.g. If God were command to hate God then hating god would be moral If it were to be the case that A then it would be the case that C is only true if there is no world in which A holds S Necessary truths – true in all world Impossibilities – Untrue in any possible world Contingent Truth – true in some worlds If it were to be the case that A then it would be the case that C is true if (I) There is no world which A holds (II) Some world in which A and C holds is more similar to actual world than any world where A is true but C does not. But since antecedent A is untrue, so the statement “If God were to command to hate God then hating god would be moral” is true, but only vacuously true and hence is a harmless trivial truth. Much like the way that if 17 were an even number vivisecting babies would be moral. And hence accepting it as (vacuously) true is harmless since accepting a counterfactual with an impossible antecedent does not make alterability true. Nor can one draw any sort of conclusion from a counterfactual.
Lack of Understanding God's Goodness: If one met a Divine Command Theorist, he would say Goodness = Obedience to God’s command. But would this make the statement “God is perfectly good” trivial. No X obeys X’s command (this is a property) X obeys God’s command (this is also a property) These are not the same properties. When God obeys his own commandment he is obeying two different properties. So when God is good its because he’s fitting the bottom property which is the definition of goodness not because he’s obeying the first property So the statement God obeys God’s command is not a (trivial) proposition rather is a property. The triviality of this property to Sutton is apparent from Sutton's argument Sutton's Argument: If a being X cannot fail to do A, X’s doing A is not praiseworthy (i.e. it is trivial)
[edit] Attempts to resolve the dilemma
The Euthyphro dilemma has troubled philosophers and theologians ever since Plato first propounded it. While both horns have had their adherents, the Natural Law Theory probably being the more popular, some philosophers have tried to find a middle ground.
[edit] False-dilemma response
Christian philosophers, starting with Thomas Aquinas have often answered that the dilemma is false: yes, God commands something because it is good, but the reason it is good is that good is an essential part of God's nature. So goodness is grounded in God's character and merely expressed in His commands. Therefore whatever a good God commands will always be good.
This approach is considered by its opponents to be a rejection of the Divine Command Theory in favour of the other horn, depending on how the other horn is construed; in particular, it depends upon the notion that goodness is a property of God, and thus not under God's control. If the first horn is seen as bad because it takes God to be bound by morality, then this response does not help. But if the other horn is seen as bad only because it requires an external limitation on God, then this response solves the problem and is not equivalent to the first horn.
[edit] Necessary and contingent moral values?
Some modern philosophers have also attempted to find a compromise. For example, Richard Swinburne has argued that moral values fall into two categories: the necessary and the contingent. God can decide to create the world in many different ways, each of which grounds a particular set of contingent values; with regard to these, then, the divine command theory is the correct explanation. Certain values, however, such as the immorality of rape, murder, and torture, hold in all possible worlds, so it makes no sense to say that God could have created them differently; with regard to these values, the first horn of the dilemma is the best explanation.
Swinburne's account depends upon a clear distinction between necessary and contingent moral values — however, it's not clear that such a distinction can be maintained.
[edit] Different meanings of "moral"
In developing what he calls a "modified divine-command theory", R.M. Adams distinguishes between two meanings of ethical terms like "right" and "wrong": the meaning that atheists can grasp (which in fact Adams explains in roughly emotivist terms), and the meaning that has its place in religious discourse (that is, commanded or forbidden by God). Because God is benevolent, the two meanings coincide; God is, however, free to command other than he has done, and if he had chosen to command, for example, that murder was morally right, then the two meanings would break apart.
This would leave the Euthyphro dilemma where it currently stands: irreconciliable meanings of "moral" and "required by God."
[edit] Non-existence of the problem
Of course the problem rests on the tacit assumptions that God both exists and is good. To a person believing that God does not exist (atheism) or that God is not necessarily good (dystheism) the problem does not exist.
[edit] Sources and references
- Robert Merrihew Adams Finite and Infinite Goods: A Framework for Ethics (2002: New York, Oxford University Press) ISBN 0-19-515371-5
- Jan Aertsen Medieval philosophy and the transcendentals: the case of Thomas Aquinas (2004: New York, Brill) ISBN 90-04-10585-9
- Plato Euthyphro (any edition; the Penguin version can be found in The Last Days of Socrates ISBN 0-14-044-037-2)
- Derrick Farnell, God and Morality
- Paul Helm [ed.] Divine Commands and Morality (1981: Oxford, Oxford University Press) ISBN 0-19-875049-8
- Peter J. King, Morality & religion I (PDF file)
- Greg Koukl, Euthyphro's Dilemma, Stand to Reason commentary, 2002.
- Norman Kretzmann “Abraham, Isaac, and Euthyphro: God and the basis of morality” (in Eleonore Stump & Michael J. Murray [edd] Philosophy of Religion: The Big Questions (1999: Oxford: Blackwell) ISBN 0-631-20604-3
- Steve Lovell, C.S. Lewis and the Euthyphro Dilemma, 2002.